Philosopher Mark Couch calls to my attention an interesting comment posted on IHE, which I here reprint in its entirety:
I am an assistant professor of philosophy in a PhD-granting department and was a reviewer for the NEH Enduring Questions grant this past year. I hope you will excuse this message's anonymity -- and its length. I reviewed about 20 or so of the applications, and recently received a list of the 20 award recipients, so I might be able to make some informative remarks about this program. I think the program gives philosophers two reasons to be worried.
These reasons have been mentioned here and there throughout the preceding comments but it may be helpful to draw them out explicitly. The first reason concerns philosophers' views about what constitutes legitimate inquiry into these "enduring questions." The second concerns how the NEH and other humanities fields view philosophy. I'll elaborate on these. When I first heard of this program, I, like many of the above commenters, had what I'll dub the "proprietary response." The proprietary response is that the enduring questions (such as "What is a good life?") are distinctly philosophical questions and that it is absurd and insulting to set up a grant program to induce non-philosophers to teach philosophy courses. However, many of the grant proposals from non-philosophers impressed me as speaking to these questions in valuable and pedagogically effective ways. Some of the proposals centered around the ethical dimensions of literary or historical figures.
Studying these lives is a way of gaining experience by proxy, such that students have a range of experiences to draw upon once they start doing philosophy more seriously. So one defense of non-philosophical courses on the enduring questions can be put in terms of remedying one of Aristotle's reasons for not doing moral philosophy with the young: they lack experience. If the question is "what is the good life?" one way to start answering that question, even if it isn't Socrates' preferred way, is with a list. Now of course one could include the study of historical and literary figures in a philosophical ethics course, but that is not very common. One applicant (unfortunately not a winner) proposed having her students spend the semester studying a single play (along with other texts) and then learning more about the characters and their motivations and interactions by having the class culminate with their own performance of the play. Maybe this sounds gimmicky to some of you, but plenty of serious moral philosophers are worried about the dominance of abstraction and general moral theories in philosophical ethics, and counsel engagement with the particulars.
This is one interesting way to grapple with the particulars. In any event, I don't remember hearing much about this kind of activity in the typical philosophy course. And if this doesn't appeal to you, there were other good ideas, such as in the truly excellent (yet, alas, non-winning) proposal for a course team-taught by an English professor and a biology professor on the question of what is human nature. Some of the proposals whose content fit the more traditional introductory ethics or philosophy course seemed detached and sterile by comparison. To sum up this first point, many of the enduring questions concern how to make sense of some aspect of life. One way to start this inquiry is to become familiar with said aspect. This stage of the inquiry need not be philosophically sophisticated to be valuable. To the extent that philosophers hold fast to the view that only they are qualified to teach courses centered around good lives, wisdom, human nature, war, religion, freedom, happiness, etc., I am concerned that we do not understand how ignorance about life and its varieties can render philosophical inquiry empty or baffling to the typical undergraduate, nor how other disciplines might contribute to philosophical learning.
That said--and this takes us to the second point--there is a limit to how much progress one can make on these questions without some kind of philosophical expertise. And while I reviewed some excellent proposals by philosophers who were grant winners (such as Mike Austin's, mentioned upthread), some good philosophical applications were overlooked. Even worse, there are signs that people at the NEH are indeed ignorant of what philosophers do, and dismissive of the idea of philosophical expertise. One application listed several of the classic questions of moral philosophy and then proceeded to complain that too few philosophers address these questions. The applicant is obviously highly ignorant of contemporary moral philosophy, his application flaunted this, and yet he is one of the award winners. Seeing something like that is infuriating. Even more worrisome than the NEH's carelessness about philosophy is the ignorance displayed by some of our colleagues in other departments. Many of the proposals by non-philosophers took up the more philosophical questions.
Yet in aspects of their applications, from the stating of the course's core questions and assumptions to the listing of the bibliographies, often I found myself frustrated at the absence of basic and helpful philosophical distinctions and the absence of classic and directly relevant philosophical texts. I only had a small sample size to work with, but the impression I got was that the view that "anyone can do philosophy well" is common in academia. This worries me. If our colleagues in other departments do not understand professional philosophy as requiring some kind of valuable expertise, that does not bode well for philosophy as a discipline. Both of the reasons for worry that I discussed in this message have to do with philosophy's isolation from other disciplines. The proprietary response is a sign that we don't appreciate what they do, and their lack of humility in regard to their philosophical ignorance is a sign that they do not appreciate what we do. In recent years in the profession there has been a fair amount of attention paid to philosophy's "public relations." As far as I know, this has been directed at getting those outside of academia interested in philosophy. But what might be even more important is a public relations campaign directed at our fellow academics.
Thoughts from readers? As usual, signed comments preferred, but you must at least include a valid e-mail address.